This important special issue of the American Journal of business law is more narrowly focused on the relationship between law and ethics in the context of business law related. Here in the trenches where the battles are fought for the commercial benefit of law, economic thought, jurisprudence and philosophy collide in a confluence of demand. The specific results of these tactics legal commitments shape the structure and content of business law and create currents that affect the global nature of legal systems. Notwithstanding this compromise, the claim that virtue ethics, unlike the other two approaches can not provide enough guidance on actions that the objection remains the most common of. This is reflected in what is becoming more commonplace in new anti-virtue ethicists moderate, namely that what we need (for a complete theory of ethics) is "a virtue ethics and ethics rules. In the early days of modern virtue ethics, it was a plausible objection. It is based on the premise that the only virtue ethics guidance could find is that you must do what the virtuous agent would do under the circumstances. It is true that the earlier literature virtue ethics offered a bit more. But then, it has been stressed by Rosalind Hurst House (1991) that generates all the virtues of an order (Do what is fair, Do what is charitable and all the vices of a prohibition (Do not do what is dishonest, uncharitable. The existence of such v "-rules" expressed in the vocabulary of virtues and vices, and thus part of a "virtue ethics", refutes (literally) on the premise which the objection was based, the likelihood, if any, is retained by the claim that an ethics of virtue must be supplemented by an ethic of rules or principles is now the ...