Given the past-history distinction, the difficulty for the historian who someway likes to arrest the past inside his/her history therefore becomes: how do you fit these two things together? Obviously how this attachment is tried, how the historian endeavours to understand the past, is vital in working out the possibilities of what history is and can be, not smallest because it is history's assertion to information (rather than conviction or assertion) that makes it the discourse it is (Historians do not generally glimpse themselves as writers of fiction, whereas inadvertently they may be). Yet because of the past-history distinction, and because the object of investigation that historians work on is, in most of its manifestations, really missing in that only finds of the past stay, then apparently there are all types of bounds commanding the information assertions that historians can make. And for me, in this fitting simultaneously of past-history, there are three very awkward theoretical areas: localities of epistemology, methodology and ideology, each of which should be considered if we are to glimpse what history is (Jenkins 2003).
Epistemology (from the Greek episteme = knowledge) mentions to the philosophical locality of ideas of knowledge. This locality is worried with how we understand about anything. In that sense history is part of another discourse, beliefs, taking part in the general inquiry of what it is likely to understand with quotation to its own locality of information - the past. And here you might glimpse the difficulty currently, for if it is hard to understand about certain thing that lives, to state certain thing about an competently missing subject like 'the past in history' is particularly difficult. It appears conspicuous that all such information is thus expected to be tentative, and assembled by historians employed under all types of presuppositions and stresses which did not, of course, function on persons in the past. Yet, we still glimpse historians endeavouring to lift before us the spectre of the genuine past, a target past about which their anecdotes are unquestionable and even true. Yet to accept this, to permit question to run, apparently sways what you might believe history is, that is, it presents you part of the response to what history is and can be (Schulz 1990). For to accept not actually to understand, to glimpse history as being (logically) any thing you desire it to be (the fact-value distinction permits this; in addition to there have been so very numerous histories) impersonates the inquiry of how exact histories came to be assembled into one form other than another, not only epistemologically, but methodologically and ideologically too. Here, what can be renowned and how we can understand combines with power. Yet in a sense this is so - and this issue should be worried - only because of history's epistemological fragility. For if it were likely to understand one time and for all, now and evermore, then there would be no need for any more history to be in writing, ...